Further, the work of the later Wittgenstein and of contemporary Continental philosophers influenced by Nietzsche and Heidegger have also helped to destroy the ideals of neutral objectivity in truth. MacIntyre largely accepts the various criticisms of Enlightenment objectivity as being wellfounded, and indeed directs his own criticisms at those like Donald Davidson who would try and win back some ground from all this talk about conceptual relativism.
See Whose Justice? It only remains in contemporary thought, argues MacIntyre, in a very weakened sense. Although the arguments and views derived from your tradition might appear weird and confused from the viewpoint of my tradition, it does not at all follow that they will do so to you or that our minimal shared rationality is strong enough to shift either of us from our own position. He wants to champion a form of naturalist theory, Aristotelianism.
This does not, he argues, open him to the Moorean charge that he has committed the Naturalistic Fallacy. MacIntyre sees three rival theories as dominating moral discourse at least in the West. He calls them Tradition, Encyclopaedia, and Genealogy. It is by belonging to a tradition, by participating in it, and being changed by it as well perhaps as changing it that a person forms a moral position. There is no other way, according to MacIntyre.
It is an illusion to think one can be a pure individual or possess a traditionless, timeless moral reason. The real choice, he tells us, is between Nietzsche and Aristotle.
Nietzsche was right, he says, in exposing Enlightenment illusions of objectivity. MacIntyre argued moral problems can be addressed within the broader confines of a cultural or religious tradition containing substantive principles concerning the meaning and purpose of individual and social life. In short, to solve moral problems one needed a set of principles richer than what pure reason can supply. More important, he argued these traditions are somewhat immunized against rational critique since reason itself was not pure and isolated from tradition.
Reason itself was, and needed to be, defined in terms of a broad context and, given the dependence of reason on tradition, it seemed impossible to use reason to undermine a cultural or religious tradition. MacIntyre's rejection of the spirit of modernity left one with a fundamental question: To what tradition does he ascribe?
His answer was quite straightforward. He was a Christian with the traditions of Augustine and Aquinas. When, therefore, he faced a moral difficulty, he faced it not as a pure reasoner but as a traditional Christian influenced by the ethics of Aquinas and Augustine. Contemporary critics of MacIntyre emphasized some of the difficulties in his position.
Three difficulties are prominent. First, given his objections to universalism, it would seem he could not ascribe to traditional Christianity since Christians of all denominations believe the gospel is directed to everyone. In short, it is a religion intrinsically universal. Secondly, our society is a pluralistic society in which there was a deep and binding commitment to individual autonomy or liberty.
It was also a society deeply committed to the principles of social welfare. These principles went a long way toward defining our culture and, thus, they may be construed as the tradition of the West. A modern pluralistic society was based on a tradition which MacIntyre criticized.
This culture was obviously very different from the cultures which spawned Aristotle, Augustine, and Aquinas. While these cultures were rich in many respects, they had little respect for individual freedom. MacIntyre emphasizes the importance of moral goods defined in respect to a community engaged in a 'practice' - which he calls 'internal goods' or 'goods of excellence' - rather than focusing on practice-independent obligation of a moral agent deontological ethics or the consequences of a particular act utilitarianism.
Plato, Aristotle, Thomas Aquinas , but also fully engaged with other forms of modern ethical systems e. Kantian deontology. MacIntyre has argued that Aquinas ' synthesis of Augustinianism with Aristotelianism is more insightful than modern moral theories by focusing upon the telos 'end', or completion of a social practice and of a human life, within the context of which the morality of acts may be evaluated.
His seminal work in the area of virtue ethics can be found in his book, After Virtue. MacIntyre converted to Roman Catholicism in the early s, and "now does his work against the background of what he calls an Augustinian Thomist approach to moral philosophy. Religion Wiki Explore. Religion portals. Sunni Islam Shia Islam. Contributing Getting Started Advanced.
The first and third of these, he says, are seldom taken into account by philosophers, and the second is frequently overemphasized. Aristotle comes in for particular criticism for denying the merit of the experiences of dependent human beings and making a virtue out of self-sufficient superiority Dependent Rational Animals , Much of the book is concerned with placing human beings in relationship to other animals, especially with regard to intelligence and rationality.
Because we are animals, we are vulnerable to a wide range of inadequacies, deficiencies, and illnesses and are in need of the help of others if we are to survive and even more help if we are to thrive. Each of us has had the experience of dependency in infancy and childhood and most of us will face physical dependency again as we age. The kind of dependency that MacIntyre focuses on is our dependency on others to learn how to be rational and how to be ethical.
This need is strongest in children, who at first simply follow whatever desires they happen to have at the moment. One of the things that parents must do MacIntyre focuses on the mother throughout his discussion of parenting, without giving any reasons for this is to teach their children that what they desire is not necessarily what is best for them at that time or what is best for them in the context of their life as a whole.
Even when we pass beyond childhood, we still need others to watch and comment on our motives and actions, to insure that those aim at what is good for us and not merely at satisfying our temporary and potentially harmful desires.
These are our friends, who provide us with insight and self-understanding, not least because they call us to account for our actions when those seem immoral, short sighted, or out of character. To provide such an account I must first reflect on my motivations and goals, and then explain them in such a way that my friend can make sense of them.
This is one of the ways in which I need other people, receive things from them, and am dependent on them. Throughout my life, other people assist me in developing the use of my reason, and I am dependent on others for this; I cannot become rational on my own. I can only grow if I can reason with and learn from others, and this requires certain traits from me: the virtues honesty, courage, and justice, for example. Each of us also finds that others are dependent on us at different times and in different ways, and we are obligated to assist them in developing the same qualities and virtues others are helping us to develop; and this assistance is itself a virtue.
We therefore find ourselves as part of a community of giving and receiving which is a network of duties and obligations. Potentially, of course, these same networks are dangerous; MacIntyre acknowledges that these structures of giving and receiving are also structures of unequal power distribution and potentially of domination and deprivation Dependent Rational Animals We must take care to see that they are not used in this way.
But this network of obligations in the service of a shared good — the development of human capacities to reason and behave virtuously — means that this kind of society resembles the polis as MacIntyre understands it. So acknowledging our nature as a particular kind of animal forces us to acknowledge our dependence on others to develop our rationality and become independent and our need to use our rationality to help dependent others hence the title: Dependent Rational Animals. MacIntyre says that each of these is a different kind of virtue: the virtues of dependence differ from the virtues of independence but are nonetheless virtues Dependent Rational Animals Chapter This in turn requires us to acknowledge the networks of relationships of which we are a part, and once we have done this we can and must deliberate about the social and political institutions we wish to create in order to promote and protect these networks.
Collectively promoting the social structures we need in order to flourish as individuals enables us to escape from false dichotomies between self-interest and the common interest and between selfishness and altruism. Practices, then, are both consequences of our nature as the kind of animals we are, when we properly understand the kind of animals we are, and forms of social order that are in keeping with our nature, as opposed to contemporary forms of social order liberalism and capitalism which are not.
MacIntyre has shown that his ideal society would be different from our own in two particular areas, politics and economics, and now it is time to consider what he believes we should do in order to bring this ideal society into being. As was stated at the very beginning of this essay, MacIntyre is writing in order to resist the modern world, including modern politics. It is instead a shared project, and one that is shared by all adults, rather than being limited to a few elites who have gained power through manipulation and use that power to gain the goods of effectiveness for themselves.
Therefore, everyone must be allowed to have access to the political decision-making process. The matters to be discussed and decided on will not be limited as they are now; they will extend to questions about what the good life is for the community and those who make it up. Politics will be especially concerned with the virtues of justice and generosity, ensuring that citizens get what they deserve and what they need.
This kind of deliberation requires small communities; although not every kind of small community is healthy, a healthy politics can only take place in a small community. Although their size cannot be precisely specified, they will be intermediate in scale between the family and the modern state Dependent Rational Animals When the community deliberates collectively about its best way of life it is choosing a telos, or final end.
And that final end will be one which reflects the needs of all the citizens, including the need to have and use the virtues, which are part of our nature as dependent rational animals.
Think back to the discussion of chess. Authority in chess is derived from a mastery of the virtues internal to the game or goods of excellence rather than external virtues or goods of effectiveness. Chess players with authority do not have authority because they dominate others, or because they have wealth or political power.
Players recognize who has mastered the virtues internal to the game, and try to learn from them. Rather than hating or resenting or fearing those with authority, they welcome and value them; the powerful seek to share their knowledge and skills for the good of the game, rather than for purposes of domination or exploitation.
All the players recognize the rules of the game that make it possible for the game to educate us in its virtues, and they follow those rules because they recognize them as necessary and desirable. They are loyal to the game, they enjoy it, and they genuinely care about those with whom they share it.
There is competition, to be sure, but it is in the service of pursuing a common good. The political community, for MacIntyre, must be this kind of community. Capitalism must be replaced or transformed, or at least ways must be found to shield individual small communities from its effects.
The ideas that the purpose of life is to get rich and that the well-being of a society can be measured by its economic production will both be rejected, for these both reflect a focus on the goods of effectiveness rather than the goods of excellence. In addition, capitalism undermines communities of all kinds, including the family; we must have a way of life that puts the common good first. There are many possibilities for how we might construct new economic systems.
The society MacIntyre prefers will have only small inequalities of income and wealth, to prevent people from being excluded from the community by their poverty or placing themselves above it on account of their great wealth, both of which phenomena we certainly see today and which Aristotle recognized in his day. If MacIntyre is correct that growing up as human beings is about learning to overcome our immediate desires and learning to see our long term good, then advertising and marketing, which teach us to give in to our immediate desires, are going to become much less effective.
Markets must be subordinated to the development of the virtues in individuals and the community, rather than the other way around, which is what happens in the world in which we now live. MacIntyre says that we can begin to work on the kinds of small communities that are capable of preserving the practices and virtues even in the face of liberal capitalism Whose Justice?
We need to focus our energies on building and maintaining the kinds of small communities where practices and the virtues have a place and protecting them as much as possible from the depredations of the modern state and modern capitalism. At the end of Three Rival Versions of Moral Enquiry, he proposes ways to modify universities and their curricula to bring them closer to the kind of communities he wants to encourage.
Small communities will also make it possible for people to evaluate political candidates in a variety of settings and judge them on the basis of integrity rather than adaptability The MacIntyre Reader We can evaluate our leaders on their actual characters rather than seeing them through the distortions of advertising and the manipulation of propaganda.
Both Marxism and Catholicism, for different reasons, critique the unbridled pursuit of wealth under capitalism. But there are many reasons to doubt that the kind of society MacIntyre promotes will turn out as he wishes. Many authors, from Adam Smith to Hayek to von Mises, have argued that attempts to control or limit markets inevitably have as a consequence attempts to control and limit human beings in ways that lead to the gulag rather than to the virtues.
This would kill initiative and innovation and lead to stagnation. Whether people agree or disagree, MacIntyre would probably take some satisfaction in the fact that at least there is an argument going on — a serious discussion about the ultimate values and way of life the community should pursue — which is typically avoided or stifled on those rare occasions when it does arise.
The next step would be to make this kind of argument a part of mainstream political discussions. In the meantime they will be the best way of life for those who are fortunate and hard-working enough to be a part of them. And of course those who, like MacIntyre, practice philosophy in his tradition must continue to strengthen and develop the arguments found in the Aristotelian tradition as it has developed through Aquinas, and continue to draw attention to the flaws and weaknesses of liberal philosophy in the hope of persuading others to change their allegiances.
This bibliography includes only the most significant books from the period beginning with After Virtue and is in chronological order. Ted Clayton Email: clayt1ew cmich. Emotivism and Manipulative Social Relations If we are to fully understand emotivism as a philosophical doctrine, MacIntyre says, we must understand what it would look like if it were socially embodied. The Concept of a Practice and the Origin of the Virtues In After Virtue , MacIntyre tries to explain another element of what is missing in modern life through his use of the concept of a practice.
Politics in a World without Morality MacIntyre argues that today we live in a fragmented society made up of individuals who have no conception of the human good, no way to come together to pursue a common good, no way to persuade one another about what that common good might be, and indeed most of us believe that the common good does not and cannot exist.
The Athenian Polis and Aristotle MacIntyre asserts that the virtues of heroic society and the heroic ideal carry forward into classical Athens, but since Athenian society is organized very differently than heroic society, this leads to difficulties. A New Politics MacIntyre has shown that his ideal society would be different from our own in two particular areas, politics and economics, and now it is time to consider what he believes we should do in order to bring this ideal society into being.
A New Economics Capitalism must be replaced or transformed, or at least ways must be found to shield individual small communities from its effects. References and Further Reading a. Primary Sources This bibliography includes only the most significant books from the period beginning with After Virtue and is in chronological order.
MacIntyre, Alasdair. After Virtue. Second Edition. The foundation of his later work and the most important of his books to read. Includes his arguments about the failures of modern philosophy and politics and how those failures might be overcome, or at least diminished, with the help of the philosophy of Aristotle and the political way of life of the Greek city-state.
Whose Justice? Three Rival Versions of Moral Enquiry. MacIntyre discusses three rival versions of moral enquiry: encyclopedia, tradition, and geneaology. It is the Thomist tradition, he argues, that proves to be rationally superior to the others.
Knight, Kelvin. The MacIntyre Reader. Highly recommended. Chicago: Open Court, MacIntyre begins this book with the claim that any moral philosophy must begin by acknowledging that human beings are a particular kind of animal with particular needs and goods that are determined by our animal nature. He then establishes what that nature is, and argues that it requires us to develop our rationality while acknowledging our dependence on others, thus providing us with a telos.
He provides a sketch of what kind of social organization would be necessary to enable each of us to fulfill our telos, and how that kind of organization differs from the organization of the modern world.
Secondary Sources Ballard, Bruce W. Understanding MacIntyre. Lanham: University Press of America, Inc. Breen, Keith.
0コメント